Phaleas of Chalcedon

Phaleas of Chalcedon (Ancient Greek: Φαλέας; fl. 5th or early 4th century BCE[1] was a Greek statesman of antiquity, who argued that all citizens of a model city (Ancient Greek: polis) should be equal in property and education.[2][3] The only surviving reference to Phaleas of Chalcedon appears in Book II of Aristotle's Politics.

Phaleas of Chalcedon
Φαλέας
Bornfl. c.5th or early 4th century BCE
EraAncient philosophy
RegionAncient Greek philosophy
Main interests
Political philosophy
Notable ideas
Equal division of property and education

A contemporary of Plato, Phaleas was one of the utopian thinkers who flourished during a turbulent period of Athenian democracy. Like Hippodamus of Miletus, he called for an equal division of land holdings and education. He saw it as a solution to the serious economic crisis that the Greek society was experiencing after the destruction caused by the Persian Wars. According to Aristotle, Phaleas argued that an equal division of land and equal education for all citizens would eliminate civil strife. Although Phaleas recognized that such a radical constitution would be difficult to implement in established cities, he believed it would be practicable in newly founded cities. In established cities, Phaleas recommended setting up dowries for the rich to give to the poor in order to level property ownership over time. In addition to equality of land and education, Phaleas proposed that all artisans be publicly owned slaves.[4]

Aristotle criticized several aspects of Phaleas' proposed constitution. Aristotle argued that while leveling land ownership would appease the poor, it would lead to insurrection among the rich who were to be dispossessed and who viewed their wealth as a right of nobility. Rather, in order to eliminate civil strife, society must educate the populace in such a way as to control want and greed; the poor must be taught to accept their station and the rich not to become overly greedy.[5] Aristotle further argued that equal distribution of land does not achieve equality of property, as other assets, such as cattle, furniture and slaves, are also of value; if property were to be regulated, one should regulate all types of property.[6]

Notes

  1. Brill's New Pauly 2002.
  2. Aristotle, Politics, 1266b30–34.
  3. Nestle, Wilhelm. "Phaleas". RE 19.2 Sp. 1658.
  4. Aristotle, Politics, 1267b15–19.
  5. Aristotle, Politics, 1266b35–1267a10.
  6. Aristotle, Politics, 1267b10–14.

References

  • "Phaleas". Brill's new Pauly: encyclopaedia of the ancient world. Vol. 10. Leiden: Brill. 2002. ISBN 9789004122598. Retrieved 17 Aug 2023.
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.