David Abercromby
David Abercromby was a 17th-century Scottish physician and writer, thought to have died in 1702.[1] Brought up at Douai as a Roman Catholic by Jesuit priests, he was converted to Protestantism in 1682 and came to abjure popery, and published Protestancy proved Safer than Popery (1686).
Works
His medical reputation was based on his Tuta ac efficax luis venereae saepe absque mercurio ac semper absque salivatione mercuriali curando methodus (1684) which was translated into French, Dutch and German. Two other works by him were De Pulsus Variatione (1685), and Ars explorandi medicas facultates plantarum ex solo sapore (1688); his Opuscula were collected in 1687. These professional writings gave him a place and memorial in Albrecht von Haller, Bibliotheca Medicinae Practicae (1779). According to Haller he was alive early in the 18th century.[2]
He also wrote some books in theology and philosophy, controversial in their time but little remembered today. But the most noticeable of his productions is A Discourse of Wit (1685), which contains some of the most characteristic metaphysical opinions of the Scottish philosophy of common sense. It was followed by Academia Scientiarum (1687), and by A Moral Discourse of the Power of Interest (1690), dedicated to Robert Boyle,[2] Abercromby's patron in the 1680s. He later wrote Reasons Why A Protestant Should not Turn Papist (1687), which has often wrongly been attributed to Boyle. A Short Account of Scots Divines, by him, was printed at Edinburgh in 1833, edited by James Maidment.[2]
Notes
- Andrew Pyle (editor), Dictionary of Seventeenth Century British Philosophers (2000), article pp. 2-7.
- One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Abercromby, David". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 1 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 43.
Further reading
- Davis, Edward (1994). "The Anonymous Works of Robert Boyle and the Reasons Why a Protestant Should not Turn Papist (1687)". Journal of the History of Ideas. 55 (4): 611–29. doi:10.2307/2709925. JSTOR 2709925.